Connect with us

Philosophical

In The Future, Should Parents Be Able To Choose The Sex Of Their Child?

Published

on

The ability to choose the sex of an unborn child stems from a desire for the child to either be male or female – and it tends to be the former. This power to decide is dangerous for the child and the rest of society, which is why this practice should not be legalised. The question we must ask ourselves in any moral dilemma, is what are the dangers, and do these outweigh the foreseen benefits? We must also consider other factors, like the difference between sex and gender.

Firstly, one could argue that this practice could be dangerous to society as it links to a form of discrimination. People tend to gravitate towards the desire to have sons more so than daughters. For example, a woman in China recently died after several abortions after her and her husband continued to discover their unborn child would be female. For children learning about this advancement of being able to change the sex of children, they could easily internalise beliefs that boys are better than girls, leading to sexist thoughts and increased discrimination. Our societal progress to promote equal wages for women, and to understand that women can choose not to have children or get married, will all be for nothing, as the work we have accomplished will be taken back a step. More girls grow up with ideas that they are not equal to boys, leading to educational underachievement due to low self-esteem, and more women choosing to stay at home. In fact, we know that in the majority of cases, attacks are generally men-on-women, and the increased belief of male superiority could even go as far as to show children that this is more acceptable than not due to toxic masculinity. Therefore, as people would prefer to have sons, children grow up believing that males are superior which creates self-esteem issues and in some cases, more physical attacks by men.

Also, there is a difference between sex and gender. Sex is biologically determined, whereas gender is a personal ‘feeling’. Therefore, there are chances that even if the baby is born male, he is transgender and wants to be referred to or even transitioned into a female. The possible intolerance for a daughter in the first place could lead to transphobia, which has in many cases, led to abuse in several forms: physical, mental, sexual and more. The idea that parents ‘love their children no matter what’ seems to have disappeared. Society has recognised that gender is a social construction and it is no longer as binary as once before. We have even been able to see the gender recognition act being processed, but this progress will be back-tracked if parents choose to determine the sex or ‘gender’ of their children. Overall, it again seems that this practice could develop another form of discrimination further – transphobia, which sets our society back as our progression towards total acceptance towards those experiencing gender dysmorphia is gone.

On the other hand, one could argue that some families simply want a daughter more than a son, or vice versa. Parents who have already had two or more children of the same sex may want to improve the dynamic and diversity of their family life by having a child of the different sex. However, some religious people could argue that it is unnatural. The parents are going against God by changing the sex pre-determined by Him, and at what cost? If God believes they should have a child of a specific sex, He will give it to them. Thus, despite some families simply wanting to choose because of family dynamics, this is not a necessity nor is it believed to be natural by some religious people.

Overall, there seems to be no benefit. It is not necessary to society or any family, and there are many dangers that are caused by the ability to choose sex. It could link to transphobia or sexism, and if the child discovered their parents chose their sex, how might they feel if they thought that their parents would only love them if they were a boy or a girl? Also, what is the point? As discussed, many families tend to want sons more than daughters, so if the world is split into a ratio of 80:20 in terms of males and females there are more negative impacts to arise. For example, many heterosexual men not being able to find a partner, and because of this, there are lower birth rates leading to an ageing population.

Noshin Jannat is a senior writer for The YLJ. She writes a weekly column every Wednesday on a variety of legal, philosophical and political issues.

Legal

Why the law should protect “true” vegans

Published

on

Something very good happened at the beginning of this decade.

On the 3rd of January 2020, Employment Judge Robin Postle ruled in Norwich Employment Tribunal that ethical veganism is now a protected philosophical belief under the Equality Act 2010. The news of this judgment circulated all over the world in such an unprecedented fashion, than in three weeks they could be read in more than 1,200 websites from more than 60 countries.

Why? you may ask. Why people in Lebanon, Indonesia, Qatar or Peru are so interested in what happened in Norwich (while they may never heard the name of this Norfolk city before)?

The reason is simple. This was a “landmark decision” of international proportions. Arguably, veganism is one of today’s fastest growing international social movements, but yet it has not reached the “policy” stage yet anywhere in the world…until now. The Norwich judgment is the first of this kind in the world, and it does not refer only to my particular belief (as I am the Claimant who brought that case), or the belief of the English vegans, but to the concept of ethical veganism in general, which is essentially the “original” concept of veganism, as defined by The Vegan Society when it was formed in 1944. Therefore, if it is recognised in Great Britain as a belief which deserve as much protection as any other protected belief, religious or otherwise, surely it should be recognised elsewhere as well, as ethical veganism is the same anywhere (it doesn’t change with different cultural backgrounds), discrimination can occur anywhere, and anti-discrimination legislation should exist everywhere (although it doesn’t yet).

This judgment doesn’t change the law, or creates an actual new legal precedent, but what it does is legally recognises that when the Equality Act 2010 was enacted, and it protected non-religious philosophical beliefs as much as religions, it implicitly included among many the belief of ethical veganism, as this passes the test created by the Employment Appeals Tribunal in 2009. This test, coming from the Grainger plc v Nicholson case, created the following requirements a judge must confirm a non-religious belief has to fulfil to be protected under the act:

  • the belief must be genuinely held;
  • it must be a belief and not an opinion or viewpoint based on the present state of information available;
  • it must be a belief as to a weighty and substantial aspect of human life and behaviour;
  • it must attain a certain level of cogency, seriousness, cohesion and importance; and
  • it must be worthy of respect in a democratic society, not be incompatible with human dignity and not conflict with the fundamental rights of others.

Judge Postle did confirm (using the words “overwhelmingly”) that ethical veganism fulfils all this criteria, and he also confirmed that I am an ethical vegan, and therefore my discrimination case based on this belief can now continue.

It is important to notice that this doesn’t mean that all those who define themselves as vegan would now be protected from discrimination, harassment and victimisation as are those who hold other protected characteristics (such as gender, age, marital status, religion, etc.). It will only protect “true” vegans. With this I mean, for one side, those who hold the belief genuinely and not just follow a temporary fashion or only “practice” the manifestation of such belief when it’s convenient to them. And for the other side, only those who follow the Vegan Society’s definition to the full, which means aiming to exclude, when practicable and possible, all forms of animal exploitation and cruelty to animals, not only those related to food production. Therefore, those who only follow a vegan diet but still want to wear clothes with animal products (such as wool or leather) or still want to visits zoos for entertainment, those are not “ethical vegans” even if they define themselves as vegan, so they would not be protected. Is this fair? I think it is, because I think society should protect more those who change their lifestyle to help others (animals suffering or the environment being destroyed) than those who only do it for themselves (to have a better health or look younger).

Ethical veganism is growing so fast because is a positive non-religious universal philosophy that tries to solve the most important problems we have in the world today: the trillions of animals that every year suffer from being unnecessarily exploited by humans, the catastrophic destruction of the environment (including global warming) caused by the animal agriculture industry, the hunger created by the waste of land and water used to raise animals for food and clothing, the severe health problems caused by the widespread consumption of animal products, and the legitimisation of abuse, exploitation and oppression as a form of progress . A society which allows to discriminate those who try to minimise their negative impact to the world, at the same time they try to help everyone else by providing a real practical solution to the world’s worse problems, is an outdated society with no foresight.

“True” vegans need protecting because unfortunately they are already discriminated, harassed, victimised, and hated by people who are blind to the real world’s problems and who are unwilling to share their privileges with those less fortunate. Those who after millennia of indoctrination think that others don’t’ matter, only they do, are ironically not from the Selfie and YouTube generation, but from the gladiators generation, the crusades generation, the witch-hunting generation, the foxhunting generation, and the factory farming generation. These outspoken institutionalised selfish “carnists” who are so triggered by the concept of veganism are who the law should be keeping “at bay” so ethical vegans can finally manifest their beliefs to the full without fear and worry, and in so doing freely attempt to significantly improve the world for next generations to come.

Surely, that is a good thing.

Continue Reading

Legal

Reckless Transmission of Covid-19: A Jail Sentence?

Published

on

With the death toll of the infamous coronavirus having recently surpassed 20,000, there is a real sense of fear propagating among the general public as to how best protect themselves, evidenced through the increasing sightings of shoppers kitted up in surgical masks. Just last week, a 57-year old man in Dudley, who claimed to be infected with Covid-19 and deliberately coughed at the staff in a local shop, was arrested under the Mental Health Act of 1983, which allows for someone to be ‘detained in the interests of his own health or safety or with a view to the protection of other persons’. However, during these extraordinary times, it may be interesting to consider whether the reckless transmission of Covid-19 could go beyond just detention by the police and indeed constitute a criminal offence. For, under section 20 of the Offences Against the Person Act of 1861 (OAPA), the unlawful infliction of grievous bodily harm (GBH) could result in up to seven years’ imprisonment. It must be emphasised, however, that while analysing the possible legal implications, it is important to bear in mind that the probability of possessing sufficient evidence of the transmissionof Covid-19 is highly limited.

Clearly, the first point for contention is whether Covid-19 can be said to constitute GBH, that is to say, the arguably ambiguous notion of ‘really serious’ harm established in DPP v Smith. Interestingly, it was ruled in R v Dica that this harm does not necessarily have to be a direct act of violence; the transmission of a disease, HIV in that case, could represent the causation of physical injury. As controversial as it may seem, therefore, prosecuting the unlawful transmission of disease in itself is not beyond the reach of the law. More strikingly, this harm does not have to be permanent or dangerous: it is up to the jury to decide the perceived level of harm done in reference to current societal norms. In reference to Covid-19, cynics may downplay the gravity of the harm given that the death rate lies at around 1%, but it is important to remember that this virus has the potential to befatal for some and so, in these cases, could indeed be seen as a really serious harm. As Weait convincingly argues, even if the physical harm of disease transmission is up for debate, the psychological harm of receiving a potentially life-threatening disease is one which the law ought to acknowledge. Therefore, it would be convincing to argue that, especially in cases where the affected has underlying health conditions or is in a greater threatened demographic, the transmission of Covid-19 could be viewed as a harm serious enough for the possibility of prosecution under the OAPA.

Of course, simply transmitting a disease alone is no criminal offence: just visualise that student who, the day before you picked up the flu, was sneezing incessantly at the back of the class, unpunished. More than just infecting you, it is necessary that the ‘infector’ show a degree of recklessness (the mens rea of the offence). As established in R v Parmenter, it is Cunningham (or subjective) recklessness which is applied under offences of GBH; this is the idea that the infector must have foreseen a risk of harm but decided to take the unjustified risk regardless. In relation to Covid-19, the jury would need to consider whether the actions of the defendant demonstrated such recklessness – whether that be, inter alia, through failure to self-isolate or, more overtly, unrestrained coughing directly at the victim. Undoubtedly, this concept of ‘recklessness’ is ambiguous and thus some feel that to criminalise this area is an example of the unnecessary pervasiveness of the criminal law, believing that only through greater education can we effectively reduce disease transmission. Moreover, it is almost impossible to ascertain what level of precaution would be needed to mitigate recklessness. Consider whether the defendant wearing a mask, as almost universally deemed ineffective by the WHO, would be sufficient. While this article aims neither to advocate nor oppose the criminalisation of disease transmission and acknowledges the uncertainty around the meaning of ‘recklessness’, it may theoretically be found that reckless transmission of Covid-19 could be within the grasp of the criminal law.

Nevertheless, in order to be reckless as to the transmission of the coronavirus, the infector would need to have relevant knowledge of their status. With access to satisfactory testing restricted and many being advised to simply stay at home if they display symptoms, it is often very difficult to know for certain whether you are infected. Hence, in order to be liable for reckless transmission, it is likely that your relevant knowledge would need to be a positive diagnosis with the virus. Having said that, the idea of requiring clear, incontrovertible knowledge is not universally accepted: Sullivan argues that wilful blindness could equivalate to actual knowledge, that is to say that if you were aware that it was very likely that you had the virus but decided nonetheless to behave in a reckless manner, then you could be liable. Although there is not concrete evidence of how a court would react in this scenario, in the unreported case of R v Adaye where a man was told by a doctor that it was very likely that he had HIV but refused to be tested, the court ruled that he could still be deemed as possessing the relevant knowledge. However, as argued by Ryan, this could result in unjust criminalisation given that the line between wilful blindness and actual knowledge can sometimes be very blurred. More relevantly, unlike with many of the prosecutions for the transmission of STDs, it has been suggested that some may have the coronavirus yet show no symptoms during the ‘incubation period’ or may even never know that they were infected. As you can see, it would be an uphill task trying to prove that the defendant knew of their status unless they had been positively tested. As a result, it would be naïve to suggest that you could be found liable for recklessly transmitting Covid-19 unless you positively knew of your status.

So, can I be prosecuted for transmitting Covid-19? Well, the law is not clear. While this article demonstrates that you could theoretically be prosecuted if you knowingly and recklessly transmitted the disease, it is not plausible to suggest that you would actually end up in jail. To prove that it was you who transmitted the disease, and not one of the other thousands infected, would be impractical and costly and so the prospects of being imprisoned are clearly almost zero. However, this pandemic serves to bring back to light wider questions about whether the criminalisation of disease transmission is beneficial for public health policy. Admittedly, this article only touches the surface and omits important situations such as the relevance of whether a family member consenting to the risk of transmission could negate an infector’s liability. Nevertheless, it aims to underline the necessity for governments to assess the most effective methods to control the spreading of the coronavirus. The wider question: is the criminal law the best one?

Continue Reading

Legal

Giving nature human rights

Published

on

Amidst an era of wide and profound natural degradation, Lake Erie, situated on the US-Canadian border, last week joined the growing list of natural sites worldwide granted the legal title of Personhood.

This move is an innovative conservation measure attempting to succeed where previous, more conventional, protections have failed. As the climate crisis and ever-increasing human encroachment and pollution drag the world’s most beautiful natural sites to the brink, many see expanding the breadth of legal personhood to include natural sites as the answer.

For decades, locals have observed the deterioration of Lake Erie with a mixture of dismay and exasperation. All other attempts to regulate the surrounding industries responsible for the mass pollution of the lake have failed. Perhaps a page has finally been turned.

Rampant run off from agricultural pesticides on the banks of the Lake is the main culprit for the immense algal blooms forming in the lakes. These ever-growing blooms of algae suffocate the lake, killing its fish and plant life. Furthermore, the lake is the main source of drinking water for hundreds of thousands of people who have seen its quality get gradually worse so that today it is borderline toxic. A radical approach to tackle all this was clearly necessary.

Though the first of its kind in North America, the creative legal move has already been implemented in various areas across the globe. Chief among these is the Whanganui River in New Zealand. Ruthlessly exploited for over a century, in 2017 the New Zealand parliament voted to pass legislation conferring legal personhood on the river, declaring it an indivisible, living whole possessing “all the rights, powers, duties, and liabilities” of a legal person.

This move was long-overdue in the eyes of the local Maori people who have always considered the river, the principal source of life for their community, a living being worthy of equal, if not superior, respect as a person. The decision was taken not only to protect a universal site of natural beauty and source of life but also for political reasons. It came as part of a broad governmental initiative to “atone for [the state’s] past wrongs and begin the process of healing”. In so doing, it was made clear that this was more than just a conservationist measure but also an attempt to come to terms with a brutal past filled with shameful exploitation and human atrocities.

This progressive sentiment from the New Zealand government is hugely encouraging for indigenous rights activists and environmentalists worldwide but is still a highly radical exception among the settler colonial nations. Though it is still a far-flung dream to imagine the US ever expressing such historical remorse or desire to make amends, more than ever under the current administration, the legal move at Lake Erie is nevertheless a hugely encouraging step forwards in recognising man and nature’s interconnectivity.

Gerard Albert, chairman of the Whanganui tribal collective, welcomed the “recognition that the river is the indivisible and living whole of Maori understanding and not the fragmented, inanimate components… that has been the European approach.” This touches on the belief held not only by the Maori but by many indigenous groups worldwide, of the interconnected relationship between man and nature. One of mutual respect, obligation and responsibility and one gaining more mainstream attention across the western world. Thanks to Extinction Rebellion and other climate justice movements, this quasi-animist belief is, for the first time, gaining traction in the capitalist societies of the West. The significance of this cannot be understated. It is in great part the western belief, stemming from a particular Christian biblical interpretation, that nature is man’s dominion to shape and plunder as he so wishes that has led the world to the ecological brink.

It is still to be seen whether these new legal measures will hold up when challenged. They are yet to be tested in their respective legal system and may well prove toothless again conventional legal attacks. Indeed, it is not yet known the scope of the new move. For example, will a river be able to sue a corporation polluting its water with toxic waste? As yet, no one really knows. Only time will tell the true significance but what is for sure is that affording legal Personhood to nature is an innovative move worth trying in a world that requires protection as never before.

Continue Reading

Facebook

Most Searched

Advertisement

Recent Posts

Trending

THEYLJ.CO.UK